Below I outline certain assumptions about the characteristics and
relations of humans that can underpin a comprehensive theory of
politics capable of successful explanation of the political
phenomena.
1. The
Theory of the Selfish Gene
This theory, associated usually with Dawkins, considers life as an
epiphenomenon of reproduction of genes and the modes of relations
between individual organisms, that can be, e.g., altruistic,
cooperative, competitive, predatory or parasitic as strategies
associated with gene that aim at nothing and exist because these
strategies give them the competitive edge and thus survive. Taking
genic point of view, as Dawkins urges us to do, obliges us to see
any behaviour as good as any, so long as it ensures the
reproduction of the gene that prescribes it, regardless of the
pain it causes to other individuals or even the carrier of the
gene. From the human point of view, it means that nature is
indifferent to morality. I will argue that this worldview,
notwithstanding the initial apprehension it causes, is necessary
to explain morality.
The reason is that, within this framework of the Selfish Gene, it
is compatible to think of morality as good for certain lifestyles
that are based on creativity and thus good for the genes that
underpin such lifestyles. Human evolution shows a clear sign of
achieving greater capacity for creativity.
I
use creativity to refer to methods of creating resources through
acquiring, transmitting and applying knowledge, exclusive of
violent or deceptive methods that aim at disappropriating what
others have created. Within this definition, most fields of human
activity can be seen as manifestations of creativity. Agriculture,
services, industry and trade all evidence the acquisition and
application of knowledge, of past generations if not the current
ones. However, I accept that someone who is inventing a weapon is
also being creative, since he is creating an item that others may
need and use. But to use this weapon to destroy or dispossess
others indicates a failure on the part of the user to create
resources or to resolve conflicts of interest with others
creatively.
I
assume that the impetus that creativity has is due to the fact
that people who can make a living out of creativity can also
afford to join alliances.
Considering morality as good for certain lifestyles implies also
that there might be some lifestyles which are not compatible with
morality and thus stand to lose because of morality. If we grant
that it is possible to find a man who lacks creativity skills to
meet his needs but who is skilful in preying on others, then,
considering that morality prohibits such methods, we should expect
that this man to lose if he was punished on the basis of moral
rules or compelled to conform to moral rules.
However, this is not a recipe for nihilism. Once we are aware that
our behaviors are unconsciously tuned to promote the interests of
genes and take into account that we have no obligation towards
them, we can allow ourselves some detachment and leeway. In the
meantime, we can consider that absolutely every human being owes
something to creativity. Creativity is what has produced
technology and civilization without which the multitudes of
humanity could not have existed. This can underpin the inference
that if we owe anything to anyone or to any human quality it is to
creativity. But creativity is not possible without adherence to,
at least, some basic moral rules which allows creativity to pay
off. This consideration can counteract skepticism that morality
might be no more than a sham, used as a tool for manipulation.
Also, by considering that humans have a built-in attraction for
beauty and curiosity for knowledge we can appreciate that many
people may decide to adhere to morality not for the sake of
morality but in anticipation of what beauty and knowledge that
themselves and others can discover, not only in nature but also in
humans. I believe that such a drive already exists and it is
responsible for giving a great passion to attempts for discovering
beauty and knowledge.
2.
Knowledge Processing
Human individuals, more than other animals, rely for their
survival, which involves competition and cooperation with other
individuals, on the acquisition, transmission and application of
knowledge (knowledge processing henceforth). The application of
knowledge in human life is evident in most what humans utilise and
thereby transform their environment. The greater the capacity of
an individual or her group for knowledge processing, the greater
is their competitive edge.
The decisive role that knowledge usually plays and human deference
to knowledge opens the way for competition and also for unfounded
and fraudulent claims of knowledge to be made that, if not
checked, may generate rewards for the claimants. This constitutes
an objective ground that favours the evolution of institutions to
validate or arbitrate between competing claims of knowledge. And
indeed, humans have evolved institutions to deal with competition
through claims of knowledge. As I will suggest later, it is the
methods of dealing with the competition through claims of
knowledge that have the most decisive role in shaping human
institutions and history.
Perhaps, human knowledge can be seen to fall into three main
categories. An essential focus for human enquiry and knowledge is
resources. It concerns physical properties of the materials and
inhabitants of the environment in which human beings live,
including the natural properties of human beings themselves, since
qualities like fertility, physique or mental capacity can have
decisive bearing on the potential for survival.
Human experience and numerous technological applications can be
seen as a part of a greater institution for validating, or
arbitrating between, different resourcal knowledge propositions.
Another part is science. Although science postdates competition
through claims of knowledge, and although science may be
foreseeing other functions, it can be viewed as the ultimate
institution that evolved to perform the systematic validation of
or arbitration between different knowledge propositions about the
physical attributes of the human environment.
There is also aesthetic knowledge. The reason that aesthetics need
be regarded as a branch of knowledge is that it guides our choices
- be it in rule-of-thumb fashion - in the course of finding what
is useful and avoiding what is useless or harmful. As such,
aesthetical feeling can be viewed as manifestation and signals of
a hardwired assumptions of knowledge of what are useful or harmful
objectively. There is no doubt that our choice of food is decided,
at least partially, on the basis of olfactory and visual clues.
Evolutionary psychologists have advanced a number of arguments of
this sort and, indeed, the argument that the attractive
characteristics of a person of the opposite sex are indicative of
and favourable for fertility, sounds plausible. Perhaps, one can
broaden the speculation further by suggesting that the attractive
features of a person may be indicative of social sensitivity and
creativity. Art in this context can be seen as the arena where
such sensitivity and creativity are displayed. A poem, for
instance, may be seen as a display or celebration of verbal
capacity and the feeling one has for words and phrases and this is
no insignificant capacity for an animal that captures much of its
knowledge through language.
However, there is no denying that considering aesthetics as a
branch of knowledge involves a broadening of the sense of the term
knowledge. The semantics need not be an insurmountable problem.
People say a child is learning to walk, and this indicates that
there is knowledge involved. Yet, a walking individual is neither
conscious of the mechanism of walking nor aware of the brain
systems and muscles involved. Similarly, we are not exactly
conscious of the criteria upon which we decide what is beautiful
or not; we are rather aware of our feelings of approval and
disapproval or attraction and repulsion. Natural science, in
contrast, is based on objective and quantitative measurements of
which we are aware. But this is not to say that aesthetics do not
correspond to objective criteria. Although it is true that our
feelings are subjective in the sense that we may not be able to
describe them and our description may not be verifiable. They are
not wayward experiences without any correspondence to anything
objective. Though true that we may not be able to convey our
feeling of certain colour but, unless there is a visual defect,
certain range of light wavelengths corresponds to certain colour,
and most people regardless of their culture concur on colour
spectrum.
The other category is political knowledge and will be discussed in
the latter sections. I call it so because of its implication in
the formation of political power. However, certain points need be
made open. The thesis of 'knowledge processing' subsumes that
human beings are capable of examining the entailments of ideas and
that they may demand an account of validity or authority of the
knowledge propositions, upon which they may reject or accept an
idea. At the basic level lies another assumption, namely, the
assumption of 'the mind of others'. But then this is not unique to
me; all moral philosophers and perhaps most social scientists make
such an assumption, though mostly implicitly.
3. The
Theory of Emotional Fitness.
This theory is based on the assumption that the evolutionary
pressure in favour of those who can fit within various social
systems like family, clan, clubs, businesses or friendships (or
more specifically RISs - see below) must have produced a human
psychology that is responsive to social value. I conjecture that
positive evaluation, inferred either from expressions, treatment
by others or self-evaluation in the light of acceptable values
constructed by others or perhaps by oneself, results in the
arousal of positive emotions such as self-satisfaction, pride and
elation which lead to a state of extroversion. Consequently, these
emotions contribute to social success and survival in the
Darwinian sense. In contrast, negative evaluation leads to shame,
guilt or embarrassment that lead to introversion, inaction and
perhaps eventually submission, which are the kind of emotions that
cause pain and dispose the individual either to reconsider the
self and others or conform and accept a subordinate position which
might evolutionary be still more beneficial than confrontation..
However, considering the important fact that individuals compete,
we should also expect a drive to manipulate and abuse these
evaluative-emotional-mechanisms in order to subordinate others and
thus further one's own cause. This means that a rival or a person
who aspires for dominance may try consciously or unconsciously to
induce negative evaluation into the rivals or challengers as an
inexpensive means of social or political control. In response, I
speculate that there can be a mechanism whereby a person tries to
restore the positive evaluation for the self. There can be many
ways to achieve this. One may try to conform to social values and
attempt to achieve favourable social recognition. One may change
the social setting to where one is assessed positively. The new
social setting can be for some a circle of sycophants, a new
political party or one's own initial social group. For more
creative people it may entail rejecting the explicit or implicit
values and attempting to develop alternatives. It may consist of
resorting to self-delusion and thus isolating oneself, as I
believe narcissists do. (Self-delusion may seem counterproductive;
however, in a moderate degree it may be advantageous if it helps
in maintaining a positive assessment of the self and thus a degree
of extroversion long enough to achieve social achievement.
Self-delusion may also be useful if it makes a person immune to
unjust social judgments or treatments.) Other methods may consist
of rejecting the negative assessment and resorting to aggression,
or applying various kinds of pressure so that the interlocutor
evinces only the positive assessments.
The quest for emotional fitness can highlight the rationality of
some moves that would otherwise be deemed irrational from the mere
economic point of view and even from the point of view of a
simplistic evolutionary assumption, which endeavors to find an
adaptive rationale for any action without taking into account the
interceding psychological mechanisms. For instance, stunts or
involvement in creativity even without obvious economic motives,
which seem outright counterproductive, can all be explained in
terms of achieving a positive self or social assessment. Likewise,
risking one's own safety to visit loved ones in desolate and
dangerous places or to rescue other people may also have the same
effect since such actions usually draw approval and because the
loved persons are usually celebrated and this consolidate the
emotional fitness.
The theory of emotional fitness also provides us with the context
to broaden the concept of need or interests. For instance, love
and affection, owing to the fact that they are expressed in the
form of celebrating the beloved, will be seen within this scheme
as consolidating factors of emotional fitness; the demand for
respect and or equality and the rejection of demeaning values and
discourses can be understood as strategies for gaining and
maintaining emotional fitness and we can expect that some people
would insist on them even at a great cost to themselves. The
broadening of the concept of need also allows us to see love,
respect and other socially important attitudes as resources for
which it is likely that some people may make great sacrifices.
Finally, and importantly in this context, the perspective of the
theory of emotional fitness allows making sense of many aspects of
life that are concerned with political (moral and ideological)
values. One such is the strong emotional valance for the concern
with these values - people, for instance, defend, sometimes
extremely violently, the values that cast a favourable light on
them and reject with equal force the values that question them.
Another is the drive that some people may have to change identity,
be assimilated or integrated into another social background when
the values do not favour them and they have no appropriate
intellectual or physical response. A third is the drive to
construct and propose a new set of values that give a better
position to the actor. As such, this theory highlights the
psychological background for concern with political values and it
contrasts favourably with Marxism, which attributes the formation
of political values to economic interests, without highlighting
the significance of values on a personal level. No wonder
therefore that Marxism fails to explain, using its own conceptual
tools, the reasons that, e.g., two persons in a similar economic
and social position may think differently and may even end up
fighting on opposite sides.
Emotional fitness theory also tells us that people are concerned
with values, though specifically with being valued favourably
according to the values that they accept. However, since some of
these values may be cruel or ideological we should expect that
individuals might participate in or condone committing of horrors.
This point has a direct bearing on policy making: to address a
social or political conflict we need to address the ideas and
values that are held by the parties to the conflict. This approach
differs markedly from the approach that sees nothing but economic
inequality as the culprit in social and political conflicts and
thus advocates economic aid, which achieves little. The failure of
economic aid in fact should not come as a surprise if it happens
that the receivers believed that the wealth of the donors is just
plundered wealth from the countries of the receivers in the first
place.
4. The
Resource Interdependency Systems, RISs
The fourth assumption that informs this political theory is the
concept that I would term 'resource interdependency systems' (RISs).
Resource here is used in a broad sense. It refers to sustenance,
nurturing, shelter, education, protection, power and even
affections, sex and moral support. In this sense the resources
include not only exogenous items but also all what can be offered
or possessed by humans whether they are physical or psychological
as long as they are needed by others. Thanks to the potential for
knowledge processing, humans can tab into many natural resources
and enjoy them. However, for this potentiality to be actualized
needs some social resources that need perhaps be originated
necessarily from within social systems, like families, clans,
clubs, business, states, gangs, which are what I call RISs. The
most basic of RISs that humans need is family. Within this system,
the relation is likely to be cemented by the emotion of love which
may be a sort of expression of genetically mediated altruism that,
as an evolutionist towing Dawkins's line may argue, disposes the
bearers to care for other bodies bearing its copies. The practical
expression of this altruism is manifested in what parents offer to
their child, which sometimes tantamount to all what they can
possibly offer. Now if we think of love as a need that for its
fulfillment a person may make even the ultimate sacrifice then the
object of love or what fulfils it should be considered as the most
valuable commodity.
As an individual gains more capacities for knowledge processing,
she might be able to form or join more RISs, such as friends,
businesses, clubs and political elites including the one that
might run a state. However, it is important to note that not all
resources and thus their providers are of equal survival value. If
we avoid interjecting morality, from the mere survival
perspective, some services and their producers can be dispensable
or replaceable - indeed, this is the reason that employees are
laid off and some espouses are changed and sometimes some people.
Moreover, while people need resources and services they may not
need or do not care, necessarily, about the wellbeing of the
producers of the resources. Humans can produce food, hunt or build
facilities but humans can also be used for labour, sex and as a
warring machine, and nowadays even as body parts for each other.
This creates a strong incentive, or pressure, on an individual to
be on one's guard, to demand moral qualities and commitments from
others, and to organize institutions for protection. The autonomy
or protection that others enjoy creates both evolutionary and
developmental pressure to evolve and develop morality - or
otherwise to develop the capacity to construct and deal with moral
propositions or even take advantage of them. Now considering that
some people, at least, are capable of producing their resources by
using creative methods without the need for predation and
parasitism, that these people would stand to benefit from building
alliances, moreover, considering also the benefits of appealing to
morality by an individual who needs moral commitment, we are,
therefore, in a position to see the basic factors that lead to the
creation of polities.
Moreover, the interest in joining the favourable RISs creates an
incentive to develop the capacities for producing resources (or at
least to look as though one is capable of producing indispensable
resources).
However, considering the emotional aspect of human life we should
decline the assumption that what matters are material resources
and brute physical and mental strength. This emotional aspect must
have been the reason that humans evolved capacities for humour,
jocularity, gregariousness, the passion for singing, dancing and
the arts, as well as the capacity to respond to emotions like
shame, guilt or embarrassment that substitute to punish
anti-sociality as well as disposing the subjects towards
self-correction or perhaps submission.
Taking the RIS perspective, has many advantages. It tells us that
a person may be interested in forming varieties of RISs but not
necessarily interested in a society, which, as ill-defined as it
is, gives the impression of a harmonious social unit. Yet in
reality a society usually subsumes varieties of RISs or subunits
that may be locked in deadly interaction. RISs can also be seen as
the institutions for which most social selection, a part of
natural selection, takes place. For instance, different
individuals may make transactions with morally suspect people
within the wider society on a one-off or brief basis, but they try
to keep these suspects out of their essential RISs and may even
back violent actions against them if they are deemed as out of
control. RISs are also the institutions for which individuals
construct and introduce moral qualities. The concern for the
safety of children or business would surely make promulgating
moral rules useful. In contrast, it is not unlikely that the same
family- or business-person tries actively to undermine the moral
standard of a rival RIS. The perspective of RISs, unlike that of
society or community, has diagnostic significance. We can expect
that, other things being equal, the more RISs whose membership a
person enjoys, the happier is that person. This might give a
useful guide as to the direction we should work in order to
improve the wellbeing of some people. Even observing the nature of
relations within RISs can give us a clue to the difficulties a
person may experience.
5.
Knowledge and Political Power
Obviously, a lifestyle dependent on creativity clashes with a
lifestyle dependant on predation and parasitism. At least some
people can use both methods. However, apparent or genuine
subscription to creativity allows the building of alliances or the
forming of RISs. Such subscription, consequently, prepares the
ground for the existence of a greater number of people possessing
greater opportunities for creative application of knowledge, which
result in having greater wealth and capacities and thus a greater
impetus in favour of yet greater creativity. Two reasons for the
prevalence of creative lifestyles over destructive or parasitic
lifestyles can be cited here. Firstly, no one can hold RIS or
alliance while professing commitment to a predatory and parasitic
way of life. This is not to say that some RISs cannot be formed
exclusively for predation and deception. However, I assume that
even within such RISs, the predators usually take a moral stance
exalting themselves and morally disparaging their potential
victims, and they may select their victims among those who are
alleged to be worthless or harmful. The other reason, which is a
consequence of the first, is simply that people who profess
morality can hold RIS. This might explain why human civilisation
has survived and also why humans become increasingly characterised
by creativity. Seeing morality as a means to promote certain ways
of life and thus the genes that inform them, casts new light on
the meaning of the expression 'morally good'. Within the context
of this evolutionary political theory, it should imply that this
good is peculiar to certain people and it is against other people
who are more successful in preying on other people rather than
producing themselves.
As said earlier many kinds of RISs can exist. Perhaps, a family
might be formed because of a sexual relation and because of kin
altruism without clear articulation of the moral rules and values
that are involved in its running. However, when many RISs, without
clear shared genetic interest between them come close to each
other and when this proximity makes it possible for some RISs or
outcast individuals to gain resources through predation and
parasitism, a need arises to articulate the moral values and build
specifically political RISs that can arbitrate between different
RISs. However, we need to take into account the following: that we
cannot be certain of the validity of many claims of knowledge of
morality; that simulation of morality introduces further
complications and that moral knowledge propositions are capable of
mobilising collective forces in favour of certain ways of life
against others. These points prepare us to expect competition
through moral propositions. Indeed, people compete to put forward
their own views of what morality is. Yet, this entails that
despite the need for a particularly political RIS, such an
organisation may fail to exercise power specifically because of a
failure to converge upon one set of moral rules.
6.
Building Model
My final main assumption is that it is possible to understand the
political process and also predict the course of history and even
that of the future by building a model of the institutions that
can provide and maintain a unified set of moral propositions
necessary for building political power. This means that the key to
understand politics is to assume that the main important step for
building political power is to provide and maintain a unified set
of moral rules and that the methods that humans adopted to achieve
this initial task have decided on the course of their history and
will also shape their future.
I
believe that two different models can be devised. If violence or
coercion were not permitted to suppress moral disagreement then
the only way out of chaos and disintegration of political power,
which would follow as a consequence of voicing moral dissent,
would be by arranging polls and by adopting tentatively or
experimentally what the majority favours. Adopting majority rule
would be necessary because it is hard to sustain any argument in
favour of undertaking minority rule. Such an argument will need
justification in terms of superiority of, at least, some persons
within the minority - this EPT assumes that humans are likely to
reject undervaluation as a reaction to protect their emotional
fitness, moreover, undervaluation entails exclusion from political
decision-making as well as earmarking for subjection to others'
political power (for instance, even a benign doubt in rationality
of some people is likely to inform placing them under the
supervision of others). However, considering also that any
majority can err, we should assume that the parties to the
arrangement will adopt special measures to ensure that any
majority decision can be revoked and a new moral rule enacted.
Among the measures that can be envisaged to be necessary are
preventing the elimination of the lives of actual and potential
dissidents, allowing access to voice opposition and perhaps
actively seeking to highlight the counterproductive cases of the
application of the current moral rules. These entail, among other
things, allowing a certain degree of autonomy to individuals and
perhaps forming a social body that monitors the application of
moral rules and also aids in highlighting adverse cases. Now
reaching this point, we can note the similarities between this
model and actual liberal democracy. Two main similarities stand
out. The actual liberal democratic institution of rights includes
the special measures suggested above and actual election of
liberal democracies is a forum in which voting of moral matters is
decided. These similarities justify considering a proposition that
actual liberal democracies may have evolved exactly for the
purpose of dealing with moral disagreement and for providing a
unified set of moral rules that allows the maintenance of
political power. But there are important differences. The actual
liberal democracies are associated with nation states. Many
writers from the right and the left argue forcefully that liberal
democracy is necessarily associated with capitalism. However, this
EPT disputes this assumption, suggesting instead that the
association is accidental. Yet, it is clear that actual liberal
democracies are associated with centralised forms of government,
borders and capital cities. None of these features are predicted
in the course of building the model. Thus for the proposition of
similarity I just suggested to be taken seriously the differences
need to be explained. This explanation is possible if we examine
the behaviour and the possible courses of evolution of the second
model that we need to devise.
The building of this second model can start from considering how
it is possible to provide and maintain a unified set of moral
rules without liberal democracy. This is possible if some people
are inculcated with the idea that people themselves are not the
source of their morality, rather it is decided by some ulterior
force. Perhaps, some people would not be persuaded, regardless of
whether their scepticism was due to acuity of intelligence or just
spite aimed at avoiding ceding power. The conceivable range of
methods to deal with this sort of person - and indeed these
methods have been and some still are in great use - consist of
buying them off, coercing them into silence or eliminating them.
Now, owing to the nature of these methods we will need to assume
that the model will face difficulties of a different nature. One
such is, how can it be possible to make people believe that they
are not the authors of their moralities? This is, unfortunately,
very easy. Even today, many scholars, let alone lay people, are
inclined to believe that morality is something out there waiting
to be discovered. This is understandable, considering that humans
are only starting to understand themselves, and this thanks to
evolutionists - which is nevertheless not yet accepted
universally.
Another issue is what to suggest as the source of morality. To
answer this question we can turn our attention to actual
experiences of humanity to see how this problem is addressed.
Religion could be said to be one institution that deals with this
matter, and surprisingly easily at that. For theistic religions,
it takes no more than stating that there is a divine force that
created humanity and this divinity enjoins certain morality. A
different approach for denying human authority over moral
decisions can be found within Marxism. Marx dismissed the
relevance of morality, considering it as a part of ideology.
Ideologies are attributed to the process of material production of
means of survival that informs the formation of forces of
production with definite relation of production. Moreover, within
the Marxist tradition it is assumed that humans are by nature
peaceful (so there is no need for morality) and it is only the
inhumane nature of class societies that corrupts people and
implicates them in crimes. As such, Marx did not consider that
morality is needed in order to establish a political power. A
third approach to divesting humans of moral authorization is taken
by nationalists and racists. In their discourses, it is suggested
that morality is the property of biological inheritance of a
nation or a race. (It is possible to construct a fictional system
of belief that attributes morality to a mystical entity outside
direct human power - in the book length manuscript which bears the
same title as the article, I have demonstrated that an apparent
benign and deceptively reassuring ideology, that is based on some
sort of evolutionism, can carry out the gory function that other
un-liberal democratic belief systems can carry out.)
We can predict another kind of difficulty that would face this
model by considering the fact that issuing moral propositions or
directives and rules is extremely significant considering the
power dimension of moral rules. That is why we should ask how it
is possible that the majority of people allow few others to decide
the moral rules that they will have to adhere to. In other words,
how is possible that some people believe in "prophets", "great
national leaders" or philosophers who decide for them what they
ought or ought not to do? In an intellectual climate, where people
are ignorant of the political process, and can believe in
superstitions and have no experience of a free press to reveal the
merits or demerits of a leader, believing in extraordinary or
mystical qualities of some leader would become easy. This is
particularly so when people, in certain circumstances feeling
disconcerted and desperate, would want to pin their hopes on
something or someone rather than on nothing.
However, if these conditions apply to some people, they do not
apply to all and some people may not be carried away. A skeptic or
hostile section of a population ready to point out the
shortcomings in the arguments and characteristics of leaders of
movements may abort the growth of the movement - this, indeed, is
my explanation for why fascists and communists did not succeed in
reasonably well established liberal democracies. That is why we
have to assume that other methods of treatment will be needed.
Economic pressures or opportunities may be sufficient for some
people to change their stance. For others, a degree of
intimidation may do. However, hardcore opponents may persist for
whom violence may be the only solution. But bearing in mind that
violence is usually associated with predation we should expect a
collective reaction against violence. To prevent this we will need
to assume that this model of institution should try to morally
condemn the potential victim. In other words, within this approach
the victim should turn into the culprit.
I
would call this model the ideological model. Examining the real
politics of the world, one cannot find a liberal democratic system
predating a few centuries-apart from the inchoate democratic
system of Ancient Greece. On the other hand, humanity has known
empires and states that go back in history for at least four or
five millennia. So if I am right in my assumptions that, at least,
all multi-RIS political systems need an institution to provide and
maintain a unified set of moral rules so that political power is
generated, and if it is true that there are only two ways to
accomplish this task, then all these pre-liberal democratic
systems must have been informed by ideologies. This assumption is
warranted considering that religions were the dominant systems of
belief in the past and that most religions in fact reject the idea
of human authorship of moral rules and moreover, most religions
condemn or at least condemned their sceptics. I would also call
Marxism, anti-liberal nationalism and racism ideologies, on the
assumption that they can support political systems without the
need for liberal democracies and without considering moral
decision-making as a central issue.
Structurally we should predict the availability of certain
essential features of in the ideological systems. These systems
need to be centralised, because a centralised organisation is
better able to deal with opposition particularly when violence is
employed. Centralisation comes about naturally within these
systems because, in fact, the ideologues of an ideological RIS
wield enormous power anyway, given that the whole power of the
legislative body is surrendered to them. In essence, to be able to
declare who and what characteristics and behaviours are good or
bad entails that the ideologue is in a position to direct the
political power against thousands of people. This means that the
ideologue will be in position to determine the lives and the
wellbeing of thousands if not millions of people. Such a person
could be expected to be the centre of hatred, envy and a target
for conspiracies or sycophancy.
Being in this position we appreciate that such people would
benefit from buffering themselves with their relatives who may be
less inclined to betray or forsake them. This introduces a system
of dominance of a family over the system and paves the way for
monarchy. This explains why even in professedly anti-monarchic
systems, such as communism, Baathism and early Islam, monarchism
came to evolve.
The effort to concentrate power should be expected to have the
potential for favouring the formation of capital cities. Since
having officialdom close ensures easier surveillance and
communication, this must at least have been the case in the past.
Such a system should not have a system of rights, which is a
characteristic of liberal democracy, as rights impede the
effective dealing with opponents.
The ideological system would also be characterized by
concentration of wealth, mainly through the appropriation of that
of dissenters'. This should be an anticipated move, considering
that a power exercise would be easier if the subjects are weaker
economically, psychologically and even physically and also
considering that economic and political powers are exchangeable.
As such, within this model we should expect the population to lose
its capacity to challenge the system and in the long run even to
feed itself. This EPT predicts that such conditions must have been
or should be experienced in all un-liberal democratic polities.
Indeed, it can be argued that the old Empires of Islam, Romans,
Babylonians as well as hundreds of others suffered such fates and
that the recent histories and present situations of the USSR, Iraq
under Saddam, and currently Cuba and North Korea do not gainsay
this prediction.
We should also expect the formation of political borders
particularly along the lines where a campaign of subjugation and
annihilation against ideological enemies developed into war and
this war came to an impasse.
It is possible to imagine an ideological system dominating the
population of a society completely, and in this case the
continuous downgrading of the economic, moral, and psychological
state of the population may lead to slavery and may develop into
cannibalism.
Change within an ideological system would not be expected to come
from inside, although opposition can happen in the form of a split
among members of the elite struggling to gain the upper hand. Thus
the political struggle within these systems is characterized by
factious fighting which may break up the system into smaller
systems. Consequently, within this model we should expect the
system to fall as a result of outside pressure. This indeed was
the fate of many Islamic empires as well as that of the Romans and
many others.
However, competition between rival ideological systems and the
struggle for survival through improving economy, weapon technology
and gaining more man power may give incentive to the rulers, or
put pressure on them, to allow some reforms. In Britain, my
expectation is that such a situation allowed the growth of
societal forces, who, through Magna Carta, could eventually
circumscribes the use of violence and this laid down the
groundwork for the evolution of liberal democracy.
Reaching this point, we are able to see the roots of the nation
state, capital city, a centralized form of government and also the
system of rights and elections. Other features, like capitalism
and parliamentarianism which I did not predict in the model, can
also be explained. Capitalism can be regarded as an accidental
feature of liberal democracy and emerged as a result of the
concentration of power including the economic which is necessary
for maintaining the political power. Capitalism reflects a moral
state of mind, rather than a necessary stage of development of
human economic relations. It reflects an indifference towards
inequality. This state of mind should come as no surprise
considering that humanity has just started coming out of an
ideological era when even taking the lives of others by the
thousands or millions seemed, and still seems in some ideological
countries, a prerogative of the rulers of the ideological group.
However, this is not to say that private property ownership made
no positive contribution. The mere existence of economic autonomy
would give some power to individuals to voice their opinion but
unrestrained monopoly of economic means undermines this autonomy
for the many.
With regard to parliamentarianism which represents the confinement
of moral decision-making to a very small elite group, it could
also be said it is reflecting a mentality that sees the current
condition of depriving the population from decision- making as a
norm and sees the political process as the prerogative of the few.
This must be a relic of a past mind set when it was the norm to
have a single person dominating political decisions.
Finally, I should say that this model has the capacity to make
more detailed predictions about the cultural and spiritual state
of populations under ideological systems that do not draw
attention currently. These and other detailed arguments are
available in the manuscript.